Why Paradigm Shift Is So Hard from Aristote
Title: Why Paradigm Shift Is So Hard from Aristotelian Metaphysics to Instancological Metaphysical Structure
The evolution of metaphysics, from Aristotle's first philosophy to modern proposals like Instancology, is neither linear nor frictionless. Shifting a civilization’s deepest conceptual grammar is akin to asking a language to switch its alphabet, or a religion to rewrite its scriptures. Despite cracks in the Aristotelian edifice long revealed by quantum physics, G?del’s incompleteness, and post-Heideggerian thought, its legacy still dominates the West’s philosophical instincts. Against this massive inertia, Instancology proposes a radically new metaphysical scaffold: structured not around being, substance, or causality, but around instance, relation, and the interplay between the Absolute and the Relative. Why, then, is this shift so difficult? This essay explores seven interlocking reasons.
---
1. Aristotelian DNA Is Coded into Western Thought
The West still thinks in terms of Aristotle, whether it admits it or not. His metaphysics embedded concepts like substance, essence, potentiality vs actuality, and four causes deep into theological, scientific, and linguistic worldviews. Even the scientific revolution, which broke with Aristotelian physics, retained Aristotelian metaphysical assumptions: that objects exist in themselves, that causality is linear, and that knowledge seeks to identify universal essences (laws, categories, etc.). This metaphysical heritage became not merely habitual but invisible—a silent framework undergirding all disciplines.
Instancology, by contrast, breaks this heritage entirely. It asserts that there is no isolated object, only relational instances; no final substance, only issuance from the Absolute (AA); and that existence is not a static being, but an ongoing relation between Absolute and Relative across four zones (AA, RA, AR, RR). To embrace Instancology is not to update a model; it is to uninstall a metaphysical operating system that has been running for 2,000 years.
---
2. Cognitive Anchoring in "Being" Over "Issuance"
Humans find it easier to believe in what “is” than in what “issues.” Aristotle’s notion of ousia—being or substance—satisfies a deep cognitive need for stability and identity. An object either exists or does not; this binary comforts the mind. Instancology, however, replaces being with instance, and further insists that all instances are issued in relation—never independent.
This shift introduces discomfort. Instead of asking “what is this thing?” Instancology demands: “in what matrix of relations does this appear, and by what Absolute issuance does it become knowable?” To minds trained in object-first thinking, such questions feel abstract or even unintelligible. But this is a case of metaphysical literacy, not metaphysical failure.
---
3. Institutional Inertia and the Authority of the Canon
Academic philosophy moves slowly—sometimes glacially. Journals, curricula, peer review processes, and tenure committees still privilege engagement with canonical figures. Publishing a work on Instancology without framing it through Kant, Hegel, Heidegger, or Quine will almost guarantee dismissal. But referencing those figures merely to gain legitimacy often results in distorted interpretations of Instancology, recasting it as a footnote to the past rather than a radical re-founding.
This institutional conservatism forms a protective wall around Aristotelian descendants, ensuring that even the most revolutionary ideas must pass through gatekeepers trained in old paradigms. The revolution is thus trapped in a loop of incremental reform.
---
4. Language Itself Is Structured in Aristotelian Categories
Languages—especially Indo-European ones—are built to express subject-predicate logic, mirroring Aristotelian substance-attribute metaphysics. We say “the moon is bright,” not “brightness-mooned.” This encodes the subject (thing) as primary and the predicate (property) as secondary. But Instancology claims this linguistic structure is itself a Relative relation (AR), not a reflection of ultimate reality.
To express Instancology authentically may require a linguistic revolution—not just in vocabulary but in syntax, grammar, and metaphor. Until then, any attempt to teach or defend Instancology will be partially constrained by a language evolved to preserve Aristotle's metaphysics.
---
5. Epistemological Habit: We Think Knowledge Is About Objects
Since Aristotle, knowledge has been tied to identifying and categorizing the substances that make up the world. Science, for instance, often proceeds as if objects exist independently, and we merely discover their properties. This object-first model has been reinforced by centuries of technological success.
Instancology breaks from this by placing relation before object, and issuance before substance. Knowledge becomes not a mirror of being, but a dynamic interaction between AR and RA, grounded in AA. The knower is no longer external to the known, but a participant in its instance-field. This requires not just a new theory of knowledge, but a new kind of cognitive humility.
---
6. Emotional Resistance to Rebirth Thinking
Instancology emphasizes the Rebirth Principle—the need to abandon inherited assumptions and regenerate cognition from the Absolute. This is not merely intellectual; it is existential. To accept that the mind, the world, and even logic itself are relative instances grounded in AA is to give up deep emotional securities. It feels like death to the ego that believes in stable identity.
In Aristotelian terms, change is accidental; in Instancology, change is essential. The world itself is issued in a Macro realm destined to die, while only the Micro realm remains. This vision threatens both scientific materialism and religious absolutism. Resistance is, therefore, not just conceptual—it is spiritual, psychological, and cultural.
---
7. Lack of Historical Precedent and Community Support
All past metaphysical revolutions—Plato’s Forms, Descartes’ cogito, Kant’s categories, Hegel’s Geist—emerged within recognizable traditions. They had predecessors, followers, and institutions to carry the flame. Instancology, by contrast, is new. It offers no traditional lineage and few institutional champions. It begins from first principles: Absolute issuance, the 2×2 structure (AA, RA, AR, RR), and the formless matrix that underlies all cognition and existence.
Such originality is its greatest strength—and its greatest challenge. Without community, education, or scaffolding, new paradigms struggle to grow.
---
Conclusion: The Path Forward
The difficulty of shifting from Aristotelian to Instancological metaphysics is not a mark against Instancology—it is a measure of how deep the former's roots run. But cracks are everywhere. Quantum entanglement, G?delian incompleteness, the limits of language, the failures of postmodern relativism, and the dead-end of analytic logicism all point to the need for a new frame. Instancology offers it: a metaphysical structure based not on substance but on instance, not on being but on relation, not on description but on issuance from the Absolute.
The shift will be slow. But as with all paradigm changes, it starts with individuals willing to see the world not as it has been inherited, but as it truly is—instanced, relational, and alive.